VW may have taken a big step towards resolving its emissions scandal in the United States with its recent guilty plea (at a cost of more than US$4.3 billion!), but its troubles in Europe are far from over. Luxembourg has launched criminal proceedings and more countries may follow after the European Commission made it clear it felt member states had not done enough to crack down on emissions test cheating.
It seems safe to assume that VW’s cheating was not the act of a single rogue engineer, but when scandals like this occur, where does the moral responsibility lie? Is it solely the responsibility of the individuals who developed and implemented the software? Or is the firm itself, which likely put pressure on employees in various ways, also to blame? If so, to what extent? And what does it mean to say that a business as an entity is morally responsible?
With the global financial crisis behind us and seemingly few lessons learnt, and as business scandals like VW’s misdeeds continue to dominate headlines, these seemingly arcane questions, once largely the domain of academics, are becoming increasingly mainstream. In our recently published book, The Moral Responsibility of Firms, we gather the thoughts of some of the world’s leading philosophers and business ethicists and find that positions differ markedly, with compelling underlying arguments on both sides of the debate – and important practical consequences.
Is there a “corporate person”?
It has become common parlance to talk about how BP destroyed the Gulf of Mexico, or pharmaceutical companies misled doctors or banks were to blame for the global financial crisis. But the idea that corporations act as if they are human seems initially quite implausible. Although companies are composed of real people, there is hardly reason to believe that individuals who place themselves into structured groups create a new and separate human-like moral agent with its own beliefs and desires. Can we really identify a corporation or any other business entity as a moral agent that can intend actions and be held accountable for its decisions? Can it act autonomously, form moral judgments and respond in light of those judgments?
No guilt, no blame
In her chapter in our book, Amy Sepinwall, a professor at the Wharton School, suggests that corporations themselves have no capacity for emotion or responsiveness to moral reasoning are therefore unable to experience guilt, and, as it makes sense only to blame those who can experience guilt, corporations do not qualify for moral agency. In other words, it is the individuals inside the corporation, not the corporation itself, who should take responsibility for actions taken in the name of a firm. This is supported by arguments put forward by David Rönnegard, a visiting scholar at INSEAD, and Manuel Velasquez, a professor of management at Santa Clara University, who insist that individual members of corporations are “autonomous and free.” Company-level policies and procedures may influence people in firms, but it is individuals who are ultimately responsible for their decisions and actions.
What then, does this view say about the role of corporate culture? If we were to scrutinise the banks, whose sale of U.S. mortgage-backed securities sparked the global financial crisis, is it sufficient to attribute all the blame to the autonomous actions of greedy individuals or should we consider the culture that facilitated it contributed to the disaster? To what extent, if any, are there grounds for laying some of the responsibility in the hands of the organisation that allowed the misbehaviour to happen and company leaders like VW’s Martin Winterkorn who may have tacitly, if not actively, encouraged it?
The dangers of blaming the firm
There is a danger that by allowing a firm to take responsibility for wrongdoings, innocent people will be penalised and the individuals responsible for the misbehaviour will get off scot-free. According to Ian Maitland, a professor at the Carlson School of Management, University of Minnesota, holding corporations morally and legally responsible can encourage firms to create opaque organisations allowing individuals to act with impunity, effectively creating “a scapegoat which diverts legal responsibility from the executives, managers, and employees who have committed wrongful acts.”
In addition, rendering corporations liable to criminal punishment as collective entities can be seen to contravene the most fundamental principles of a liberal society. John Hasnas, a business professor at Georgetown University, notes that by punishing the firm, through fines or business restrictions, we are more likely to be punishing those innocent of wrong-doing, including employees, consumers and shareholders.
Meeting expectations
Taking an opposing view, others argue that a corporation has a voice of its own, distinct, if not different, from those of its members. It is this organisational voice which prompts Philip Pettit, a professor of Politics and Human Values at Princeton University, to insist that corporations are indeed fit to be held morally responsible, particularly in regard to actions that breach commonly shared expectations.
It is also worth considering the possibility that a firm may be morally responsible even if its intentions are not fully shared by all of its members, as suggested by Michael Bratman, a philosophy professor at Stanford University. This brings to mind banks as described by John Steinbeck in The Grapes of Wrath: “faceless monsters, something more than men …every man in a bank hates what the bank does, and yet the bank does it.”
This is not to suggest that individuals cannot be held responsible at the same time. It is fair, for example, to expect that a corporation should be held responsible for distributing contaminated food, while simultaneously arguing that employees who were negligent in the exercise of their duties should be held responsible for their part in the scandal as well.
The idea of corporate moral agency and whether corporations can be treated as individuals was first raised by another contributor to the book, Peter French, a philosophy professor at Arizona State University, in his 1979 paper, The Corporation as a Moral Person. Although much has been written since this seminal work, the practical consequences of the issue have expanded and the debate continues to rage.
Common ground
Despite philosophical differences that will continue in the years to come, most scholars of business ethics agree that corporations should be doing more to create a culture where bad behaviour is neither condoned nor ignored, and where misdeeds are not covered up but are attributable to both individuals and organisational factors. Better appreciation of moral responsibility in firms will allow managers to structure internal incentives, rules and policies to achieve the economic objectives of firms in an ethical manner. It will also help in providing an appropriate external legal framework to encourage good business conduct.
N. Craig Smith is the INSEAD Chair in Ethics and Social Responsibility at INSEAD, the Programme Director of INSEAD’s Healthcare Compliance Implementation Leadership Programme and a specialist professor at the INSEAD Corporate Governance Initiative.
Eric W. Orts is the Guardsmark Professor at the Wharton School of the University of Pennsylvania in the Legal Studies and Business Ethics Department.
-
View Comments
(3) -
Gio Wiederhold
I am surprised that the Supreme Court decision in `Citizens United' was not cited. (I have not seen the book yet). If we are to endow Corporations with the the rights of `people', we should also burden them with moral and social responsibilities.
And hiding such responsibilities by creating and having subsidiary corporations, fully under their control, is akin to slavery, and should also now be disallowed,Anonymous User
One of the most critical differences between organisations and individuals in this area is the type of punishments we can apply to them. I wrote on this in my 2016 book Pariahs: Hubris, Reputation and Organisational Crises https://www.amazon.co.uk/Pariahs-Hubris-Reputation-Organisational-Crises/. We can deprive people of liberty, even life or limb in some jurisdictions. The equivalent punishments for organisations are rare (total removal of licence to operate). But both organisations and individuals suffer a more subtle form of punishment that can be likened to the ancient Greek ostracism; not being seen as socially acceptable, having reduced influence or brand power etc. These knock on effects go well beyond the individual organisational actors responsible for bad behaviour and stay with brands for years, even decades.
-
Leave a Comment
Anonymous User
12/05/2017, 05.16 pm
This is an attempt to provide perpetuity to bad corporate culture. Penalising the people allows the culture to go on without being penalised. Both should be prosecuted and punished. The share holders should be penalised for not having a proper management. How can individuals pay for the huge losses made by corporate actions? How can individuals be protected from the power maniacs from becoming scapegoats? Corporates have cultures and these cultures breed people and their reactions.